• Entertainment
  • Environment
  • Information Science and Technology
  • Social Issues

Home Essay Samples Life

Essay Samples on Ignorance

Examples of ignorance is a bliss and origin of the word.

The word Bliss originates from German and Middle English language and associates with extreme happiness and joy. To feel Bliss literally means to be in the state of ecstasy or in spiritual joy. The meaning of the word can also be represented as a metaphor...

  • Linguistics

Knowledge & Understanding Of Ignorance In A Bible

The Republic contrasts forms, which is knowledge, form opinion, represented by appearances and its benefits in leadership. Knowledge, from a biblical basis is acquired through the Holy Spirit as a gift. In Theological-Political Treatise, knowledge is the basis of understanding the role of a state...

The Philosophy Of Ignorance And Knowledge In Buddhism

In order to prepare for the job interview, I had to hack into Buddha’s iPhone. At first, I did not know what I was looking for, but for some reason, something was telling me to do it. When I was looking through the phone I...

Motives That Drive People Towards Discrimination

Why do people discriminate against others? What is the motive? What do they hope to gain? If we understand the answers to those questions, it can help us stop discriminating against others, and enable us to understand and help those who discriminate against us, people...

  • Discrimination

An Essay on Liberal Arts and Sciences: Ignorance is Bliss

The statement, ignorance is bliss implies that not having information about something negative makes one happy. Ignorance might be motivated or natural due to inadequate education or limited access to information. Some people find motivated ignorance to be invaluable especially in avoiding information that they...

  • Liberal Arts Education

Stressed out with your paper?

Consider using writing assistance:

  • 100% unique papers
  • 3 hrs deadline option

The Invisible Man: The Problem of Social Blindness and Ignorance

Invisibility sounds like a great super power that anyone would want. Even best of us can get annoyed by this world and sometimes just wishes everyone would leave them alone and stop bothering them, but not everyone wishes that. Some might be wishing for the...

  • Invisible Man

The Ignorance of Hitchiking in the Into the Wild by Jon Krakauer

Have you ever wanted to go exploring out in the wild all by yourself? If so you might want to change your mind. Based on Jon Krakauer’s novel, “Into the wild”, The author explores the life of a young man named Chris McCandless who hitchhikes...

Socrates' Ignorance to the Mythological Concept

Myth has been known to play an important role in the lives and beliefs of people throughout time. Myth is often more closely associated with ancient Greece and its use in telling their history and creation stories. People would worship the many Greek gods and...

The Ignorance of Reality in the Ancient Times

Two prominent and correlating idioms of today are widespread throughout society. Firstly, that “Ignorance is bliss”. Secondly, that “what you don’t know can’t hurt you”. We live in a society dominated by these common phrases. Demonstrated in ancient times by two complacent and stubborn brothers...

  • Ancient Civilizations

Salem Witch Trials as an Example of Extremism and Ignorance

Scattered through the history of humanity are certain episodes of inexplicable extremism. In some cases, it is strongly linked to the culture of a society, but in others it is merely the fruit of a seed planted by something or someone more important, that is,...

  • American History
  • Salem Witch Trials

Best topics on Ignorance

1. Examples Of Ignorance Is A Bliss And Origin Of The Word

2. Knowledge & Understanding Of Ignorance In A Bible

3. The Philosophy Of Ignorance And Knowledge In Buddhism

4. Motives That Drive People Towards Discrimination

5. An Essay on Liberal Arts and Sciences: Ignorance is Bliss

6. The Invisible Man: The Problem of Social Blindness and Ignorance

7. The Ignorance of Hitchiking in the Into the Wild by Jon Krakauer

8. Socrates’ Ignorance to the Mythological Concept

9. The Ignorance of Reality in the Ancient Times

10. Salem Witch Trials as an Example of Extremism and Ignorance

  • Personality
  • Personal Experience
  • Perseverance
  • Barbie Doll
  • Affordable Housing

Need writing help?

You can always rely on us no matter what type of paper you need

*No hidden charges

100% Unique Essays

Absolutely Confidential

Money Back Guarantee

By clicking “Send Essay”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement. We will occasionally send you account related emails

You can also get a UNIQUE essay on this or any other topic

Thank you! We’ll contact you as soon as possible.

ignorance and knowledge essay

Knowledge and Ignorance 

ignorance and knowledge essay

By Jaafar Bouhlal   Updated on March 03, 2023

Introduction

Epistemology

Intellectual Humility

Dialectic Method

Ethics of Belief

Ignorance and Learning

Knowledge and Ignorance is a central theme in philosophy and has been explored by many thinkers throughout history. Here are some of the most important axes related to this topic:

Epistemology: Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that deals with knowledge and belief. This axis would explore different theories of knowledge, such as empiricism and rationalism, and how they relate to the pursuit of knowledge and rejection of dogmatism that is central to Socrates' philosophy.

Intellectual Humility: Socrates' commitment to the pursuit of knowledge was rooted in his recognition of his own ignorance. This axis would explore the importance of intellectual humility in the pursuit of knowledge, and how it can help individuals to avoid dogmatism and confirmation bias.

Dialectic Method: Socrates' dialectic method involved asking a series of questions to arrive at a deeper understanding of a concept or idea. This axis would explore the dialectic method and how it can be used to promote the pursuit of knowledge and to challenge assumptions.

Ethics of Belief: The ethics of belief is concerned with questions about the justification and responsibility of belief. This axis would explore how Socrates' philosophy relates to the ethics of belief, and how his emphasis on the pursuit of knowledge can inform ethical decision-making.

Ignorance and Learning: Socrates believed that recognizing our own ignorance is essential to the pursuit of knowledge. This axis would explore the relationship between ignorance and learning, and how Socrates' philosophy can be used to encourage lifelong learning and intellectual curiosity.

Epistemology is a central axis in the topic of knowledge and ignorance because it explores the nature, scope, and limits of knowledge. Socrates' philosophy emphasized the importance of questioning assumptions and examining one's own beliefs, which can be seen as a form of epistemological inquiry. This axis would delve into different theories of knowledge, such as empiricism, which holds that knowledge comes from experience, and rationalism, which holds that knowledge comes from reason and intuition. It would also explore how Socrates' approach to epistemology can inform contemporary debates about the nature of knowledge and how it is acquired. For example, how do we know what we know, and what are the implications of our epistemological assumptions for our understanding of the world?  

Intellectual humility is a concept that emphasizes the importance of recognizing the limitations of one's knowledge and being open to new information and perspectives. In the context of Socrates' philosophy, intellectual humility is central to the pursuit of knowledge and wisdom. Socrates believed that true wisdom comes from recognizing one's own ignorance and striving to learn more, rather than assuming that one already knows everything. This requires a willingness to admit when one is wrong and to be open to new ideas, even if they challenge one's existing beliefs.

Intellectual humility is important because it helps individuals to avoid dogmatism and confirmation bias, which can limit their ability to learn and grow. By being willing to acknowledge their own limitations and the possibility that they may be wrong, individuals can more effectively evaluate evidence and arguments, and make more informed decisions. This can be especially important in fields such as science, where new discoveries and insights are constantly emerging, and in politics and social issues, where there may be multiple perspectives and interpretations of complex problems.

Socrates' dialectic method is a process of inquiry that involves asking a series of questions to arrive at a deeper understanding of a concept or idea. The process begins with a hypothesis or belief that is put forward by one person, and is then subjected to scrutiny and questioning by another. Through a process of back-and-forth dialogue, the two parties work together to refine their understanding of the concept or idea.

The dialectic method is a powerful tool for promoting the pursuit of knowledge and for challenging assumptions. It encourages individuals to think critically and to examine their beliefs and assumptions in a systematic and rigorous way. By engaging in dialectical inquiry, individuals are able to arrive at a deeper understanding of complex issues and to develop more nuanced and sophisticated perspectives.

The dialectic method has been used in a variety of fields, including philosophy, education, and law. In philosophy, it is often used to explore abstract concepts and to arrive at a clearer understanding of complex philosophical problems. In education, it is used to promote active learning and to encourage students to think critically about the subjects they are studying. In law, it is used to test the validity of legal arguments and to help lawyers to identify weaknesses in their opponent's case.

Socrates' philosophy emphasized the importance of pursuing knowledge and recognizing one's own ignorance. In the context of ethics, this can be seen as a commitment to making informed and justified beliefs. The ethics of belief is concerned with the justification and responsibility of belief, and how we can ensure that our beliefs are well-founded and not harmful to others.

Socrates' approach to ethics involved questioning assumptions and examining one's own beliefs and values. By doing so, individuals can strive to ensure that their beliefs are well-founded and ethically responsible. The Socratic method of questioning can also be used to challenge others' beliefs and to promote critical thinking and intellectual humility.

In contemporary discussions of the ethics of belief, Socrates' emphasis on the pursuit of knowledge and intellectual humility can be seen as relevant and valuable. By encouraging individuals to question their own beliefs and to strive for greater understanding, his philosophy can help to promote responsible belief formation and ethical decision-making.

"Ignorance and Learning" in the topic of Knowledge and Ignorance focuses on Socrates' belief that recognizing one's own ignorance is the first step towards acquiring knowledge. Socrates believed that individuals should never assume that they have all the answers, and that true wisdom comes from recognizing the limits of our knowledge and striving to learn more.

In this axis, the relationship between ignorance and learning is explored, and how Socrates' philosophy can be used to encourage lifelong learning and intellectual curiosity. By embracing intellectual humility and a commitment to questioning assumptions and beliefs, individuals can continuously expand their knowledge and understanding of the world around them.

This axis also highlights the importance of critical thinking and the ability to evaluate information and ideas. Socrates' dialectic method involved questioning assumptions and challenging beliefs in order to arrive at a deeper understanding of a concept or idea. This approach can be applied to many areas of life, including education, politics, and personal relationships, to promote more thoughtful and informed decision-making.

Overall, this axis emphasizes the value of ignorance in the pursuit of knowledge, and how a willingness to admit what we don't know can lead to greater learning and personal growth.

Plato: 'Ignorance, the root and stem of all evil.'

Ignorance, the root and stem of all evil.

Ignorance, the root and stem of all evil. This powerful quote by Plato encapsulates the inherent relationship between knowledge and morality. In its straightforward interpretation, the quote suggests that ignorance is the fundamental cause of all wrongdoing and immorality. When individuals lack knowledge or understanding, they are more likely to engage in harmful actions or contribute to societal ills. This concept highlights the importance of education and the pursuit of knowledge in fostering a more just and virtuous world.However, to delve deeper into this topic, let's introduce the philosophical concept of moral ambiguity. This notion challenges the black-and-white view that ignorance leads unequivocally to evil. Moral ambiguity signifies the existence of actions or situations that are neither purely good nor purely evil but lie on a moral continuum. It recognizes the complexity of human nature and the intricate web of factors that contribute to our choices.While Plato's quote emphasizes the negative consequences of ignorance, there are instances where ignorance may not necessarily lead to evil. Consider a child who unintentionally breaks a valuable antique, unaware of its significance. The child's action may cause damage, but without malicious intent, it would be unjust to label it as inherently evil. The key distinction here lies in the absence of knowledge and intention.Conversely, there are situations where knowledge and understanding can be used to perpetuate evil. A well-educated individual may possess the skills and knowledge necessary to manipulate and deceive others, leading to acts of cruelty or injustice. In this scenario, we witness how knowledge can be wielded as a tool of evil, challenging the idea that ignorance is solely responsible for wrongdoing.While ignorance can certainly contribute to fostering an environment conducive to evil, it is important to acknowledge the multidimensionality of morality and the multifaceted nature of human actions. The extent to which ignorance plays a role in perpetuating evil depends on various factors, including intent, context, and the individual's capacity for self-reflection.To truly address the root causes of evil, we must strive for a society that values not only the pursuit of knowledge but also the cultivation of empathy, compassion, and critical thinking. By fostering an educational system that encourages moral development alongside intellectual growth, we can equip individuals with the tools necessary to navigate the complex ethical landscape.While Plato's quote serves as a poignant reminder of the importance of knowledge in combatting evil, it is crucial to explore the nuances and intricacies surrounding this topic. By embracing the concept of moral ambiguity, we can enhance our understanding of the complex relationship between knowledge, ignorance, and morality.In conclusion, Plato's quote, "Ignorance, the root and stem of all evil," encapsulates the fundamental role that lack of knowledge plays in perpetuating wrongdoing. However, it is important to recognize that moral ambiguity exists and challenges the notion that ignorance alone leads unequivocally to evil. By fostering a society that values both knowledge and moral development, we can strive for a world that is not only informed but also compassionate and just.

Plato: 'Opinion is the medium between knowledge and ignorance.'

Plato: 'there are three classes of men; lovers of wisdom, lovers of honor, and lovers of gain.'.

ignorance and knowledge essay

You are using an outdated browser. Please upgrade your browser or activate Google Chrome Frame to improve your experience.

The Oxford Eagle

Opinions: Knowledge or ignorance

Published 12:00 pm Friday, February 19, 2016

By Oxford Eagle Contributors

P eople often begin statements with “I think”— even though they may not have even thought of the issue until the moment before their mouths pop open.

Since, however, what follows originates in their brains, they claim ownership of the idea. Thinking, in short, does not slow down some folks from speaking poppycock.

Email newsletter signup

Consider the other way many statements begin: “In my opinion.” Likely the speaker feels that has a more authoritative ring about it. If he happens to be a Supreme Court justice and is speaking of a case on the docket, his opinion carries far more weight than does his saying “I think Coke tastes better than Pepsi.”

Hearing assertions that something is the opinion of someone should set off an alarm in our heads. What we think of the opinion is in direct proportion to what we think of its announcer.

A dunce with an opinion will impress us far less than a learned person saying the same thing. Be not in a hurry to accept the opinions of anyone as absolute truth or good judgment. People still exist who believe the Earth is flat. And some folks maintain that all the images about men on the Moon were faked in a giant studio in California.

Huge differences exist between a parental opinion that Jethro Pithfroggle should date their daughter and a judge in a court of law’s opinion of issues in a case, one in which he has balanced the words of the law and the actions of the accused. But even so, judges reviewing the same facts in a case may well make diverse judgments.

As most issues in court devolve to a Yes or No, the opinions of the various judges usually fall into one or the other judgment, based on the understanding (opinion) of each judge as to the words of the law and the actions of the person before the bar.

At least we can hope that judges do their homework and don’t reach their conclusions over a six-pack of cold beer watching a football game. If the latter be the case, then their opinions are no more valid than every yelling fan in the stands.

A search for observations about the meaning and value of opinions yields some fascinating comments. Here are two from favorite writers of mine.

Hippocrates commented: “Science is the father of knowledge, but opinion breeds ignorance.” Surely he refers to folks who offer opinions willy nilly on just about everything they encounter without clothing any of it in the threads of careful thought. Plato observed that “Opinion is the medium between knowledge and ignorance.” I think he’s suggesting that an opinion (hopefully predicated on assessment of information at hand) reveals progress toward knowledge and a distancing from pure ignorance.

But that’s just my opinion!

T.J. Ray, a retired professor of English at the University of Mississippi, can be reached at [email protected].

More Columns

ignorance and knowledge essay

Private, consumer-owned utilities are best option

ignorance and knowledge essay

Try harder approach has lost its power

ignorance and knowledge essay

Summer football weather a lot like life

ignorance and knowledge essay

No problem drinking good bourbons

Friends2follow, special sections.

What is your opinion of Day Light Saving Time

  • Wish it was all year long
  • Wish we had standard time all year long

View Results

  • Local Sponsored
  • Classifieds
  • Small Business
  • Submit a News Tip
  • Submit a Photo
  • Sign Up for Our E-Newsletter
  • © 2024, The Oxford Eagle

Ignorance - Free Essay Samples And Topic Ideas

Ignorance denotes a lack of knowledge, awareness, or understanding. Essays on ignorance might explore its psychological, social, or philosophical dimensions, its impact on individual and collective decision-making, or the societal mechanisms that perpetuate ignorance. Discussions might also delve into the concept of willful ignorance, the relationship between ignorance and prejudice, or the methods and importance of combating ignorance through education and information dissemination. Analyzing ignorance provides an insightful exploration of the barriers to understanding and the potential pathways to fostering a more informed and aware society. We’ve gathered an extensive assortment of free essay samples on the topic of Ignorance you can find in Papersowl database. You can use our samples for inspiration to write your own essay, research paper, or just to explore a new topic for yourself.

Animal Farm and Ignorance

George Orwell's Animal Farm is a classic cautionary tale that exposes Soviet Russia for being a totalitarian nightmare through the use of satire. In Animal Farm, the animals of Manor Farm rise against their oppressive master Mr. Jones only to have another even more oppressive master, Napoleon the pig. Throughout the book, the animals become miserable and lose more and more rights as the pigs become corrupt. The animals on Animal Farm allow this to happen as they are constantly […]

Ignorance and Lack of Knowledge

Ignorance and lack of knowledge can lead to other forms of slavery in today's society. Teaching how to think, not what to think will lead to a healthier, more productive society. Better critical thinking prevents social outcasts and helps us to grow in culture. Frederick Douglass learned how important education would be to a society, and shares his story in Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass, an American Slave. Douglass searches for a pathway from slavery, through education, to […]

Implicit Vs Explicit Attitudes

Implicit and explicit attitudes are the levels of our attitudes that set our opinions, ideas and attitudes towards other people, objects and situations in our everyday life. Implicit attitudes are the attitudes formed in the unconscious. These attitudes exist without us knowing and are involuntarily formed. Explicit attitudes are the ones we can easily report on, they are formed at a conscious level and we are greatly aware of them. An example is when you meet someone new and instantly […]

We will write an essay sample crafted to your needs.

Thesis: Racial and Implicit Bias Plays

Outline Thesis: Racial and Implicit Bias plays a significant part in how individuals are sentenced in our Justice system. Introduction Argument: Racial bias has been an ongoing issue for years, occurring in many different parts of the world. Racial bias not only occurs with people of color, but people of religion or even people of different economic backgrounds. Despite the modern transition that society has taken, society has still struggles with overcoming or creating a solution to resolve this crisis of […]

American History : Racism, Discrimination, and Prejudice

Throughout America’s history, racial profiling has continued to plague this country. Racial profiling refers to any actions initiated based on the erroneous presumption that individuals from a particular group are more likely to engage in illegal activity than people from other groups (Pg. 3.6). Many have questioned whether actions against specific minorities have changed over time, or whether just the issues of discriminatory practices differ. But the central problem stays the same. Given America’s long history of racism, discrimination, and […]

Prejudices and Forms of Racism

Ideas about the typical features of other nations depend on the forms and variety of contacts with them. In this case, the results of those interactions may be not only biases but also prejudices. The latter are formed based on inflexible stereotypes, which are unfounded negative attitudes towards people (Lustig and Koester 152). Prejudices interfere with communication since their carriers demonstrate open hostility and even aggression towards the object of prejudice, which is defined as discrimination (Lustig and Koester 153). […]

Serial Killers Ted Bundy

The Life 'I'm the most cold-hearted son of a bitch you'll ever meet' (14 Chilling, n.d.). “We serial killers are your sons. We are your husbands. We are everywhere. And there will be more of your children dead tomorrow” (14 Chilling, n.d.). Ted Bundy told Ann Rule, “Society wants to believe it can identify evil people, or bad or harmful people, but it's not practical. There are no stereotypes” (Ted Bundy, n.d.). “There lots of other kids playing in streets […]

The Perils of Ignorance: Society’s Battle with Misinformation

In today's rapidly evolving world, misinformation has become a pervasive force, clouding our judgment and distorting our understanding of reality. At the heart of this issue lies ignorance, a formidable adversary that thrives on uncertainty and preys on the uninformed. From conspiracy theories to pseudoscience, the consequences of ignorance are far-reaching, sowing seeds of doubt and discord within the fabric of society. One of the primary drivers of ignorance is the lack of critical thinking skills. In an age where […]

The Conundrum of Ignorance: how Blind Spots Mold our Understanding

In the quest for knowledge, the shadows of ignorance loom large, casting doubt on our perceptions and shaping the contours of our comprehension. It's a paradoxical dance where what we don't know guides our journey more than what we do. This enigmatic interplay between ignorance, enlightenment, and interpretation forms the bedrock of our cognitive landscape. Ignorance, far from being a mere absence of information, serves as a fertile ground for exploration and revelation. It's the fog that envelops our minds, […]

The Perils and Paradoxes of Ignorance: a Scholarly Examination

Ignorance, though often perceived as a mere absence of knowledge, represents a complex and multifaceted phenomenon with profound implications for individuals, societies, and the world at large. As a scholarly critic, tasked with dissecting the intricacies of ignorance, it becomes imperative to explore its various dimensions, from its origins and manifestations to its consequences and potential remedies. At its core, ignorance can be understood as a lack of awareness or understanding, stemming from various sources such as misinformation, cognitive biases, […]

Additional Example Essays

  • How the Roles of Women and Men Were Portrayed in "A Doll's House"
  • Positive Effects of Social Media
  • Importance Of Accountability
  • Oedipus is a Tragic Hero
  • Medieval Romance "Sir Gawain and the Green Knight"
  • Analysis of Letter from Birmingham Jail
  • Anne Bradstreet's "The Prologue" Analysis: A Reflection on Gender Inequality
  • "A Doll's House" as a Modern Tragedy
  • Poems “The Negro Speaks of Rivers” and “Still I Rise”
  • My Personal American Dream
  • A Critique of Tone and Diction "A Doll's House"
  • The Unique Use of Literary Devices in The Tell-Tale Heart

1. Tell Us Your Requirements

2. Pick your perfect writer

3. Get Your Paper and Pay

Hi! I'm Amy, your personal assistant!

Don't know where to start? Give me your paper requirements and I connect you to an academic expert.

short deadlines

100% Plagiarism-Free

Certified writers

Education and Ignorance: Between the Noun of Knowledge and the Verb of Thinking

  • Open access
  • Published: 29 March 2020
  • Volume 39 , pages 577–590, ( 2020 )

Cite this article

You have full access to this open access article

ignorance and knowledge essay

  • Tomasz Szkudlarek 1 &
  • Piotr Zamojski 1  

11k Accesses

6 Citations

1 Altmetric

Explore all metrics

In this paper we look at the relations between knowledge and thinking through the lens of ignorance. In relation to knowledge, ignorance becomes its “constitutive outside,” and as such it may be politically organised in order to delimit the borders of the right to knowledge [the “ignorance economy,” see Roberts and Armitage (Prometheus 26 (4): 335–354, 2008)]. In this light, the notion of a knowledge-based society should be understood as a society structured along the lines of knowledge distribution: the rights of possession of and access to knowledge demand that ignorance is planned and executed as the condition of their establishment. In relation to thinking, ignorance appears differently. According to Rancière, the teacher's ignorance conditions the student's appearance as Anthropos, a being who can be asked: what do you think about it? Hence, we are dealing with the ambiguity of ignorance which seems to be both the criterion of social exclusion, and the condition of emancipation. Following this thread with reference to Heidegger's discourse on thinking, we would like to explore the possibility of comprehending knowledge and education beyond the relations of ownership and demands of productivity. Following Rancière, we may say that thinking—as displacing the notion of ignorance—stands in the position of “politics” and questions the ways knowledge societies are structured as “police orders” along the lines of knowledge possession and exclusion.

Similar content being viewed by others

ignorance and knowledge essay

Coercion by Necessity or Comprehensive Responsibility? Hannah Arendt on Vulnerability, Freedom and Education

ignorance and knowledge essay

Education and Certainty: On the Importance of Education in Fethullah M. Gülen’s Thinking

ignorance and knowledge essay

Complicating Gert Biesta’s Account of Subjectification: Žižekian Negativity and Buddhist Śūnyatā

Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.

Preliminary Remarks

The connection between ignorance and education, traditionally construed in the framework of the Enlightenment crusade against ignorance, has been invigorated in recent years by numerous references to Jacques Rancière's provocative book where teacher’s ignorance is seen as a condition of emancipatory education, and where inequalities between students’ intellectual capacities should be ignored rather than turned into a target of pedagogical intervention. According to Rancière ( 1991 ), the teacher's ignorance conditions the student's appearance as Anthropos , a being who can be asked: what do you think about it? We will refer to this Rancièrean position later in the paper. However, there is one more context in which ignorance has been discussed and which we want to emphasize. Originally, it appeared in the debates on knowledge economy that highly influenced the tone of educational debates and the blueprints of education policies in recent decades. In that particular iteration, knowledge is seen as capital, and restrictions in the access to knowledge, which one may call the production of ignorance, like patent policies or the enforcement of intellectual property rights, are seen as the condition of securing the (economic) value of knowing.

The shifts and possible collisions between the various modes of ignorance relate to the rearrangement of the dominant understanding of education. The Modern imaginary, where ignorance was supposed to be overcome by the pursuit for knowledge through universal education and lead to social emancipation, has been displaced by the discourse of knowledge economy and its emphasis on skills necessary in the production of knowledge that contributes simultaneously to a distribution of ignorance. These interrelated shifts are in the background of our interest in using the lens of ignorance in the investigation into the relations between knowledge and thinking and how these affect our educational and political imaginaries.

Knowledge and thinking are at the core of what we know as education. As we will speak of them extensively further in the paper, it should suffice now to give a practical example to illustrate their somewhat problematic relations in today’s education driven by the market logic, where high-stakes testing has become the ultimate instrument of assessing its validity. In conversation with our students we have heard that some of them were given a peculiar piece of advice concerning their strategy of answering test questions in secondary school finals: if you do not know the answer to a particular question, do not think and proceed to questions you can answer right away; later will you have time to come back to those problematic ones. However anecdotal it is, this piece of advice points to a serious question of the status of thinking in education that seeks accountability and, therefore, must privilege the countable.

Another distinction that we speak about arrived in the process of writing this paper. Very quickly have we encountered a problem with some inconsistencies of language. The first part of our paper addresses the notion of knowledge, and here we speak of structures and borders, of knowledge seen as a product which has a market value, of politics (in the traditional sense of the word) and economy as the powers which define education in terms of investment. We speak of knowing that becomes reified, commodified, that is dreamt of as a “thing” that can be managed and exchanged for other things. In the second part we speak of thinking which, in fact, starts with things. But these things are thought of as interesting as long as they trigger processes: they make us think and such thinking dissolves the solid; it positions us in-between what there is; it reminds us of the very process of being as flowing through beings. Interestingly, the language of these two parts adjusts itself not to where they start, but to that towards which they aim: it “follows” them. In the first part it follows from processes (like learning) to objects, structures, exclusions and borders. In the second part, it departs from objects towards things and thinking, which brings us close to the very flux of being. The language of the first part of the paper is thus organised around nouns, while in the second part it oscillates around verbs.

A difficulty with theorizing education, we think, is that it cannot be narrated in one language. It has to speak both of structures and of processes, it has to shift between the solid and the liquid. In this respect, as we shall conclude, it operates close to what Rancière describes as the tension, or oscillation between “police” and “politics,” between what Laclau and Mouffe called “politics” and “the political,” and between what Heidegger called “the ontic” and “the ontological”. Remote as these distinctions originally may be, they all speak to the productive tension between that which “is” (like Heidegger’s beings, or the ontic) and the very process of their becoming: the Being of beings, or the ontological in Heidegger’s language. What really matters, and what always slips through our articulations and cannot be made clear, is the very relation between the two, “the third” in between. It is tempting to think that this is where education is positioned as the mediating possibility: in this particular case, between the noun of knowledge and the verb of thinking.

Knowledge—Ignorance

The way we think nowadays of the relations between knowledge, politics and education has been strongly influenced by the work of Michel Foucault. Even though Foucault did not speak of education other than as of one of the many sites and practices (like instruction, examination, etc.) where disciplinary power grows to the status of the defining logic of the modern state, the position of education, broadly understood, in his theoretical constructions is far stronger. As Keith Hoskin ( 1990 ) once noted, “the operation of power—knowledge needs a third term: … can that term be other than an educational term?” (p. 52). Footnote 1

The current variety of the knowledge—politics connection is also strongly mediated by education. It has been informed by the discourse of the knowledge society and its preceding concepts, like the knowledge-based economy or the information society, and these notions refer to education with an unceasing frequency. The vision of the knowledge society is not clear, however. It connects vague concepts and metaphors that form an ideological structure which implies, roughly speaking, that the knowledge economy builds (or needs) a knowledge society composed of life-long learning individuals and organisations, that people’s knowledge and skills are valuable assets in such societies, and that the best way of providing for economic growth and social welfare is investing in their learning. In some manifestations of this discourse, human capital investment, as guided by the logic of competition, is balanced by investments in social capital; therefore, it is not only individuals, but also their communities, families and cultures that need investment, that learn, and that therefore “count”. In general, the links between knowledge, politics and economy are inevitably mediated by education, usually re-labelled (with important negative consequences, see Biesta 2006 ) as learning.

This discourse, including its educational component, is clearly dominated by economic rationality to the extent of “genre colonization” (Leitch and Roper 1998 ). However, it has its socially conscious, more spiritual and utopian dimension. This dimension has been expressed in the discourse of social capital, in future-oriented sociological predictions (for instance in Daniel Bell’s forecast that postindustrialism will promote policies oriented towards public good rather than towards cost reductions and economic rationality, Bell 1976 , as cited in Jessop 2008 ) and in such globally circulated documents as the famous UNESCO report written under the guidance of Jacques Delors ( 1996 ). The authors of this report speak about education as “the necessary utopia” believed capable of resolving tensions between the global and the local, the universal and the individual, between tradition and modernity, long-term and short-term considerations, competition and equality of opportunities, between the expansion of knowledge and the limited capacities of its being absorbed by individuals, and—last but not least—between the material and the spiritual (Delors et al. 1996 ). Fully aware of the pressure of economy and of the practical expectations educational audiences have of schools, the authors stress the social, the existential and the ethical as the remedies for the risks and damages brought by the rapid increase in knowledge production, globalization and economic uncertainty. And yet, in spite of its holistic and humanistic attitude, their report—on the rhetorical level, transmitted already by the reference to “treasure” in title of the book—subscribes to the economic rationality which it claims to transcend. This connection is made explicit in a parable the authors use to explicate the nature of “treasure” in learning. Using La Fontaine’s fable on a ploughman who buried treasure in his field to prevent his children from selling the land, they conclude that nowadays it is learning rather than laborious cultivation of land that counts. This transformation of treasure strictly reflects the transformations of capital in modern societies. Investment in land and labour were the factors of production in the classic economy. Delors’s economy is a knowledge economy that depends on the “collective ability to leverage what …. citizens know” (Neef 2009 , p. 5). Delors and his colleagues hope that learning/knowledge will lead from focusing on economic growth to human development (title of Chapter 3 of the report), as well as to a world society and democratic participation. However, economic rationality has costs.

The policies that are involved in this economically informed ideology include competing ideas of investing in people and their knowledges, on the one hand, and cost reductions on the other. As Western economies compete globally with cheaper states with lower wages and less abundant welfare provisions, in neoliberal policies it was cost efficiency rather than growing investment that in fact became the chief aim of reforms in the public sector, which still—in spite of the long-lasting efforts to “rationalize” it along the lines of “new public management”—caters to a vast segment of educational provisions. The dominant, globally promoted solution to this conflict is private investment to supplement deficiencies in public expenditures. For instance, the rapidly growing demand for higher education qualifications was met in many countries with liberalization of state regulations that facilitated the establishment of private, tuition-based higher education institutions. In Poland, for instance, about 300 such institutions were founded in the 1990s, and their demand for academic faculty was resolved by allowing university teachers in public universities to engage in “double full time” employment. Between 1990 and 2005, the number of tertiary education students increased five times, with a comparatively minimal increase in numbers of academic teachers—a 64% increase between 1990 and 2010 (Stankiewicz 2018 , pp. 180–181).

Apart from inconsistencies in the daily practices of the knowledge economy, like mixing the rhetoric of investment in human learning with permanent cost-reduction policies, there is a fundamental difficulty with how we understand the guiding notions of this ideological position: the concepts of the knowledge society, the knowledge economy, knowledge workers, and even the very concept of knowledge are far from clear, not only in theoretical investigations, but also in policy documents. For example, the call for proposals in the EU’s 6th Framework Programme Footnote 2 lists such research areas as “Improving the generation, distribution and use of knowledge and its impact on economic and social development”, “Options and choices for the development of a knowledge-based society” and “The variety of paths towards a knowledge society”. Further, in the section on specific objectives, we are encouraged to “examine the public and private good characteristics of knowledge and to better understand its functions in the European economy and society.” (FP 6 Specific Programme…, 2004 –2006, p. 7). In other words, we need to research and promote the development of a knowledge-based society, but we have no clear idea of what a knowledge society is.

The figure of the knowledge society appears to be, in this account, a rhetorical figure. In terms of Ernesto Laclau’s ( 2005 , 2014 ) theory, it is an empty signifier. In Laclau, the role of such signifiers is to provide ground for political identities in conditions of social heterogeneity, or the fundamental lack of defining logics which could guide attempts at the reconciliation of conflicting social demands. Because society cannot be construed by logical means (Laclau is critical of the Hegelian tradition, and of Marx in particular here; there is no historical logic or structural determination that would define the course of social changes), political identities must be construed rhetorically. Such notions as “nation”,”democracy””social justice” or “knowledge society” cannot be precisely defined, and it is precisely because of this impossibility that they can operate as integrating factors, uniting scattered and conflictual demands into hegemonic policies.

What this juxtaposition of the promotion of knowledge society with Laclau’s theory suggests is that knowledge, learning and education are apparently used as empty and hegemonic signifiers nowadays: they rhetorically create the foundations of one of the nowadays competing political totalities. The discourse of the knowledge society helps to give meaning to such processes as the loss of jobs in industry or the precarization of employment among large cohorts of higher education graduates (Standing 2011 ). It hides behind its elevated rhetoric the divisions and exclusions which build “really existing” knowledge societies. Every social structure is built of differences, and the construction of the knowledge society depends not only on the lines of knowledge production, innovation and learning, but also on the lines of knowledge exclusions. Knowledge can only be defined in relation to the lack of knowledge, to ignorance as its “constitutive outside” in Laclau’s terms, as that which defines its limits, and, thus, marks its territories. Critical theories have long spoken of the destruction, appropriation and exploitation of indigenous knowledges and of the exclusions from knowing, as well as of the narrowing domain of knowledge commons, which nowadays have to be purposefully reconstructed and kept alive as fringe, avant-garde projects of cultural alternatives. The humanistic dimension of this discourse—here represented by Jacques Delors’s report—obliterates such exclusions and subsumes the structure of knowledge inequalities, produced as such in the course of turning knowledge into capital, into the all-inclusive utopia of global learning for global citizenship.

To put it succinctly, the construction of knowledge in contemporary knowledge societies implies the operation and the construction of ignorance. It relates to the transformation of knowledge production and distribution from common knowing and curiosity-driven creativity, the results of which are shared in “knowledge commons,” to profit-driven and procedurally-controlled industrial knowledge production in enclosed domains, followed by protected ownership rights. If knowledge is to “count”, that is, if it should function as an advantage in market competition, it must not be accessible to anyone for free.

The capitalization of academic knowledge affects academic institutions in numerous ways, but its most general impact can be described as undercutting the classic idea of the unity between research and education. In a research project run in four European universities (Dahlgren et al. 2007 ), several aspects of such separation were identified. One illustration is a case reported by one of the students in a university in Poland. A part-time academic teacher, a psychologist also working in a private consultancy company, interrupted her presentation during class to announce that she could not give the students more details because that would constitute selling her knowledge too cheaply. Instead, she invited them to her private company, which provoked indignation on the part of the students. The interview providing this information was conducted in 2002, when such cases were scarce. In 2015, the same university changed the employment rules for its research staff, and all contracts were supplemented with clauses that prohibit employees from publishing research results and from including them in course content until an internal office decides whether they might be commercially valuable.

One of the hypothetical interpretations of such cases in the aforementioned research is that we are witnessing a shift in what can be called “institutional pacts” linking universities with their social milieus (European Commission 2005 ). The emerging pact would be split into two different traits, mediated by two separate “products” of academic work. Both relate to the construction of what Etzkovitz and Leydesdorff ( 1997 ) called a “triple helix” of relations between the world of academe and its political and business milieus. The first pact would link the university to industry on the corporate side, and it is mediated by knowledge production. The second pact would link the university to industry on the labour side, and this one is mediated by skills production .

This separation seems to be supported by more and more evidence nowadays, and its theoretical conceptualization can be found in Marxist and post-Marxist approaches to the knowledge economy. The classic account on the emergence of capitalist economy assumes that there were two necessary conditions to be met: the production of capital, and the production of the working class (Marx 1999 [1887]). The latter was based on the enclosure of common land and the eviction of “commoners,” so that they had no legal means of survival other than wage employment. The worker is, in this perspective, a person who has nothing but his/her hands to sell. It is often claimed that the current transformation of knowledge into capital involves a similar movement (e.g. Phillips 2005 ; Zeller 2008 ; Jessop 2007 ). The massification of higher education is aimed at the production of knowledge workers, and as such they do not have to be equipped with advanced knowledge, nor are they expected to have it by their employers. If today's economy is driven by knowledge production , its possession cannot be expected of its workers. What is needed instead is that they have the skills necessary for such production (Szkudlarek 2010 ).

In this respect, the knowledge economy and its correlate knowledge society emerge within a logic similar to that which guided the emergence of earlier forms of capital. Jessop ( 2007 ) describes the commodification of knowledge, including the resistance to its devastating effects, as following the same stages as those that could be identified in the process of turning land, labour, and money into factors of production and capital in earlier phases of capitalism. The current tendencies to, on the one hand, subordinate knowledge to measurable “impact factors”, to integrate it into the flow of monetary capital (knowledge-technology transfer policies), to expand the intellectual property rights regulations, etc., and, on the other hand, the emergence of the “knowledge commons” movement, especially in its more mainstream varieties, like open access publications, present exactly the same logic as that pertaining to the commodification of earlier forms of assets. Both these movements are part of the same political logic of knowledge capitalism and they clearly repeat earlier developments of the system.

In this context, the split between skills education and knowledge education in academic institutions should be read in a radical sense, as a condition of the construction of knowledge capitalism. Its development implies the production, distribution, and management of ignorance as the border of knowledge enclosures. As Joanne Roberts and John Armitage write ( 2008 ),

the knowledge economy is precisely rooted in the production, distribution, and consumption of ignorance and lack of information. What we are suggesting, then, is that the so-called knowledge economy is one wherein the production and use of knowledge also implies the creation and exploitation of ignorance. For not only knowledge but also ignorance now plays a main role in the formation of advanced global capitalism. (p. 345)

To put it differently, when knowledge, instead of being a common good that overcomes ignorance and enables emancipation and rationalisation of social relations, becomes a commodity that one can produce, sell, or purchase, it cannot be shared freely. It starts to be clear that some people have to stay ignorant about certain matters; that knowledge economy, and with it economically controlled education, is about distribution of who knows and who doesn’t know what, rather than about popular enlightenment. Education in Modernist sense, i.e. as acquisition of knowledge and the construction of emancipated peoples is being displaced by the knowledge economy’s emphasis on skills and the production of knowledge workers that are ignorant about that knowledge which makes market advantage possible. In other words, the functioning of a knowledge society and a knowledge economy requires making particular persons ignorant about things that concern them, in order to do business or implement a policy (cf. Proctor and Schiebinger 2008 ).

The Leap into Thinking

Ignorance, as the constitutive outside of the discourse of the knowledge economy and the knowledge society, is thus incorporated and managed by its very logic. It is included as excluded (cf. Agamben 1998 ). But does this mean, however, that the discourse of the knowledge economy and the knowledge society does not have an exterior that delimits its presence? On the contrary. What should draw our attention is the absolute absence of thinking within its limits. As not matching the structure of that discourse, thinking is removed from sight. This happens by conceiving knowledge and ignorance in terms of an opposition.

Being opposed, knowledge and ignorance refer to the difference between power to control and being excluded. In this instance, knowledge is an advantage, a desired feature of the subject, being decisive in determining its social, political and economic potency. Hence it is understood as something one possesses and manages: capital. Having knowledge means being aware of things and being able to control them, that is being able to perform the power that knowledge gives (cf. Bacon [ 1620 ] 2000 ). Being related to power, knowledge is an advantage that marks the superiority of its owner, both over the subject of knowledge, and over the ignorant.

However, lack of knowledge, as a state of not being aware of things and of not being able to control them, not only signifies those who are themselves under the control of others. Being ignorant means also being put in the position of being ignored, being not taken into account, being placed out of sight. In this instance, education is conceived in terms of enlightenment, as the move from ignorance towards knowledge, from inferiority towards superiority: the move of emancipation.

Of course this will never happen: nature itself makes sure of it; there will always be delay, always inequality. But one can thus continually exercise the principle of reducing it… (Rancière 1991 , p. 119).

Indeed, as expressed above, according to Jacques Rancière, setting in motion a practice based on the assumption of inequality leads not to the emancipation of anyone, but to the verification of inequality itself. Since having knowledge is an advantage, a property of a person (in both senses) that makes him/her superior to those deprived of it, education, as the move from ignorance towards knowledge, defines the relation between the master and the student in terms of subordination, as the relation between those who have knowledge and those who do not have it (yet). But such a relation, Rancière ( 1991 ) argues, is not emancipative, but reproductive: it reproduces the inequality which it assumes, by making education “an indefinite process of coming closer. Never will the student catch up with the master, nor the people with its enlightened elite” (p. 120).

Education can emancipate, but this requires a different assumption shaping the pedagogical relation: that we are all of equal intelligence. Only if we assume equal intelligence a priori, can it become true in educational practice. However, the equality of intelligence is verified through the performance of the equality of ignorance:

…whoever wishes to emancipate someone must interrogate him in the manner of men and not in the manner of scholars, in order to be instructed, not to instruct. And that can only be performed by someone who effectively knows no more than the student, who has never made the voyage before him – the ignorant master. (Rancière 1991 , pp. 29–30).

So it is the equality of ignorance that conditions the verification of the equality of intelligence (cf. p. 31), as it is the ignorance of the master that conditions the student’s appearance as Anthropos , the being who can be asked: “what do you think about it?” (p. 36). In such a way, the intelligence of the student reveals itself to itself, nurturing the experience of being able to (cf. Masschelein and Simons 2013 ).

But is this ignorance simply opposed to knowledge as not-knowing? On the contrary, the ignorant student knows her language, her trade, her tool, and their uses (Rancière, 1991 , p. 36, cf. p. 28)—what she lacks is the awareness of her intellectual capabilities. The ignorant master knows how to interrogate her students and judge their attention (pp. 29–31), but she does not possess the knowledge about the subject of the lesson. The equality of ignorance does not, therefore, mean an intellectual emptiness of not knowing anything, but it concerns something from the world that is to be examined; it concerns the subject of thought.

Ignorance—Thinking

Hence, Rancière not only indicates the link between intelligence, ignorance, and thinking, but he also points to thinking (using intelligence) as the realm in which the opposition between knowledge and ignorance falls apart, the realm in which what is understood as knowledge and ignorance is being displaced.

We believe that this displacement can be grasped with reference to the notion of inter-esse , and that it eventually points beyond the issue of emancipation toward the matters of concern or attention to the world. In order to make that clear, we will now turn to Martin Heidegger’s lectures on thinking ( 1968 ). According to him we think because “some things make an appeal to us to give them thought, to turn to them in thought: to think them” (p. 6).

So it starts with a thing. Naturally a thing is not an object. It is not made for use in our everyday trade and traffic (cf. Heidegger 1962 , p. 439), it is not functionally involved in [ Bewandtnis ] other objects (p.115), is not ready-to-hand [ Zuhandenheit ] (p. 98). An object [ der Gegenstand ]—something which stands over against (Heidegger 1977b , p. 162)—is an effect of re-presentation [ Vor-stellen ], which is being set upon [ stellen ] for ordering [ bestellen ] as standing-reserve [ Bestand ] (Heidegger 1973 , p. 87, 97; 2000 , p. 72, 83; 1977a , p. 17). An object is a resource not to think about, but to be calculated in our enterprises (cf. 1977b ).

By contrast, the thing refers to “anything that in any way bears upon men, concerns them, and that accordingly is a matter for discourse” (Heidegger 1971 , p. 174). So if objects are managed , things are posing questions . The thing gathers meanings of human concern; it focuses people’s attention not as a resource ( standing-reserve ), but as a self-standing and intrinsic part of their world.

Therefore the thing is thought-provoking ; it gives us to think (Heidegger 1968 , p. 4, 6); it is the beginning of thinking. In order to think one has to move from surrounding objects of daily disposal towards a thing calling on us to think (p. 115).

Heidegger writes:

“Thinking is thinking when it answers to what is most thought-provoking” (p. 28).

Originally this sentence says:

“Das Denken denkt , wenn es dem Bedenklichsten entspricht” (Heidegger 1952/ 2002 , p. 30). Footnote 3

This could be rendered literally as:

“Thinking thinks when it responds and corresponds to what is the most important to think about.”

First of all, we must acknowledge Heidegger’s leitmotif, ontological difference, turning us from being [ das Seiende ] towards Being [ sein ]. Thinking, in his argument, is not conceived of as a noun [ das Denken ], but as a verb [ denken ]. It is something that happens, proceeds, moves, and so it cannot be grasped with the help of intellectual tools delivered by a Western metaphysics that perceives what stands-still and is a result of something else, what is stable, closed, and can be calculated, ordered and managed – an object (cf. Heidegger 1973 , 2000 ). Thinking is not an object to possess. It is not an outcome that could be owned. It is not someone’s desired feature, a piece of capital increasing one’s possibilities in life. Thinking is a path, a way of being, one of which one can be deprived.

Let us repeat:

Thinking, therefore, is a response to a call of the thing to turn towards it in thought. Thinking is a response to something in the world that is thought-provoking, that gives us to think (Heidegger 1968 , p. 4). It is a relation to a thing that inclines us towards itself, touches and concerns us, as that which is the most serious [ das Bedenklichste ], what is most to be thought about. Therefore, thinking is a gift from the world that requires a kind of attention that is sensitive not to the attractiveness and functionality of objects, but to the seriousness and importance of the thing. Thinking requires being interested in the world; that is, it requires to be inter-esse : “to be among and in the midst of things, or to be at the center of a thing and to stay with it” (Heidegger 1968 , p. 5).

To be interested does not mean to control, to manage objects (revealed in the ordering mode as standing-reserve), but to listen, to be attentive, to be near, to be in the neighbourhood (Heidegger 1968 , p. 12, 17; 1971 , p. 166, 177). Heidegger calls this attention as being drawn .

At first sight, such a way of being could be opposed to ignorance. Inter-esse signifies letting appear, being turned to, paying attention to, and not ignoring (the world or a thing). However, in such a case ignorance does not simply mean being unaware of things (as it was when ignorance was opposed to knowledge), but it also means not paying attention—which seems to be also the case of knowledge concerning objects in the realm of Enframing [ Ge-stell ].A technological mode of revealing the concealed, in which all that presents itself appears as an object (“objectness,” as Heidegger calls it; Heidegger 1977b , p. 163) is not inter-ess e. It orders the re-presentations of things as a standing-reserve of Ge-stell . Therefore, such knowledge is not interested in things, is not paying attention, that is, it ignores everything that does not fit its frame. Paradoxically, it could thus be called ignorant.

Does this mean that thinking is opposed to ignorance? On the contrary: ignorance makes the movement of thought ongoing. However, this movement requires ignorance to stem from inter-esse , that is, it requires ignorance to provoke the knowing being into being drawn by the thing of its interest.

In other words: thinking requires a play between knowledge and ignorance, which makes us both aware and attentive, but simultaneously not sure and without power to control. In Heidegger’s ( 1968 ) terms, it is about the withdrawal of the thought-provoking thing:

What withdraws from us, draws us along by its very withdrawal, whether or not we become aware of it immediately, or at all. Once we are drawn into the withdrawal, we are drawing toward. What draws, attracts us by its withdrawal. (p. 9)

We are attracted to a thing because of the play between what we know and what we do not know. We are paying attention to a thing because of what we do not know, and because of what we are aware of. Both, knowledge and ignorance, drive the movement of thought. However, we are talking here about knowledge that is aware of its limits (of its own ignorance), and about ignorance that is interested, is paying attention, is being drawn. Ignorance that does not ignore.

The withdrawal of what is thought-provoking means that being drawn never reaches its fulfilment. Therefore, thinking is infinite, radically open and, in a way, unproductive (cf. Masschelein 1996 ). So it does not end with a result that embodies its nature, purpose, or sense. Thinking is not encompassed by its product—in fact, it has not got any product at all. Being drawn into what withdraws as thought-provoking, that is as the most serious thing to think about, does not have its “natural” end. Naturally, one who thinks can stop the movement of his/her thoughts and turn away from the thing of his/her interest. However, stopping does not mean resulting in or producing. Therefore Heidegger ( 1968 ) notes:

Thinking does not bring knowledge as do the sciences.

Thinking does not produce usable practical wisdom.

Thinking solves no cosmic riddles.

Thinking does not endow us directly with the power to act. (p. 159)

But does not thinking bring something to our world? Is being unproductive something more than just being empty, being meaningless? What is the sense of thinking?

Let us turn to Hannah Arendt ( 2003 ) here, who reminds us of one of the similes Socrates applied to himself: a gadfly (p. 173). Thinking is a wind , she repeats, following him (and Heidegger), that unfreezes solidified convictions. “Thinking is equally dangerous to all creeds and, by itself, does not bring forth any new creed” (p. 178).

It is therefore destructive in nature; it dismantles the prescribed order of things, disintegrates our knowing; and so it is a painful experience, like a bite of a gadfly to those rooted in, or attached to the current form of status quo . Thinking is dangerous, disruptive; it is an excess that exceeds what is expected, acknowledged, acquired. And although it does not bring forth any new creed , it opens up a space for the new to appear. Hence, apart from its disruptive side thinking is an affirmation of potentiality and refers to an educational imaginary of study practices (Lewis 2015 ; Vlieghe 2013 ). Footnote 4

Following Rancière, we may say that thinking, as displacing the notion of ignorance, stands in the position of “politics” not only by questioning the ways knowledge societies are structured along knowledge possession and exclusion, but also by making room in the “police order” for the new to come.

In Jacques Rancière’s political theory, the social world is constituted by two aesthetics. The first one is a categorising, or mapping structure, which distributes social beings along the lines of visibility, audibility, or, in a general sense, availability to the senses. Some things are visible, some other are not. Some humans are visible and audible, some other ones are not. Their visibility is possible in certain places and certain times and impossible in other ones. Subjects can be seen and heard when they appear in the right time and the right place, and it is just some subjects who can be seen/heard in particular places. Such an aesthetic, such rules of the division of the sensible (in Rancière’s language), Rancière calls “police” ( 1999 , 2010 ).

The second aesthetic is that of disruption of the first one. It resorts to demonstration, to the appearance of the “wrong” people in the “wrong” places, to claiming space and time for the presence of those who were not expected to be there or to speak. It disrupts the police order and creates conditions for its reconfiguration. This aesthetic is called “politics” by Rancière.

The two modes of ignorance we have referred to in this paper are rooted in these two aesthetics. Ignorance, thus, appears “in the mode of exclusion,” as the constitutive outside to the knowledge economy, and, as such, it is absorbed to that economic realm as an object to be managed in a way which secures the commodification of knowledge. Ignorance also appears “in the mode of emancipation” in a Rancièrean sense, as linked with thinking and, therefore, involved in an interplay with knowledge that moves the Anthropos towards the thing and its call to give it a thought. As we have suggested in the introduction to this paper, the first of these modes finds its expression in the aesthetic dominated by nouns: it speaks of ignorance as opposed to knowledge, which itself is seen as plural and property—bound objects to be managed. In this aesthetic—the “police” aesthetic of a knowledge society—the reification and commodification of knowledge and the rearticulation of knowledge as capital find a “natural” setting. By the same token, the production and distribution of ignorance become a means of social exclusion, as the ignorant is placed in the position of being ignored. The same mode is one of the key aesthetics of contemporary educational practice, where knowledge is also parcelled into separate chunks, which can be represented, listed, classified, transmitted, absorbed, digested, and excreted in the form of ticks on test sheets, and where ignorance can be battled, marginalised, eradicated, and simultaneously produced, distributed, and ranked.

The second mode appears to be more complex in this respect. As we have suggested, its aesthetic oscillates around verbs , and it speaks not about an opposition, but about a play between knowledge and ignorance, therefore displacing their meanings from the “police” aesthetic of properties, placements, positions, and structures, towards movements, events, and ruptures of “politics.” Knowledge and ignorance are in play; they are intertwined as someone’s being aware and paying attention, as knowing ignorance, not ignoring and being ignored, but staying among the things of interest ( inter-esse ), being attentive to, concerned for, drawn into what withdraws. Being in someone’s turn toward a thing which is calling for attention, ignorance and knowledge drive the movement of thought that disrupts the stand-still of the structure of the status quo , and—as such—makes the thing/the world open for renewal. Therefore, in the aesthetics of “politics,” the play of the ignorance that does not ignore and the knowledge that is aware of its ignorance, opens up a space for the experience of being able to happen. In this case, education might be understood as time and space for an unproductive being drawn by what withdraws as the most serious and thought-provoking, by the thing of one’s interest. It requires being attentive, sensitive to what appears in the neighbourhood of our Being as calling to give it a thought. Such education is driven by the question: what calls us to thinking?

In this section we are using excerpts from a previously published chapter (Szkudlarek 2016 ), where the relation between knowledge society and ignorance is discussed more extensively and systematically.

Framework Programmes have been the main agenda for financing large, collaborative, internationally-based research projects within the EU and associated countries.

Fully acknowledging the skills of F. D. Wieck and J. Glenn Grey, who translated Heidegger’s Was heißt denken? , we have decided, nonetheless, to recall the original of this phrase because we wish to refer to those meanings that, in the case of this particular sentence, require a literal rendering.

Following Giorgio Agamben’s philosophy, Tyson Lewis ( 2015 ) gives an account of studying in terms of an interminable exploration of some-thing, that preserves a particular ignorance (stupidity), and doesn’t lead to any fulfilment (is not productive), but enables pure potentiality, i.e. (im)potentiality. For more elaborated theorisation of the connection between Heidegger’s concept of a thing and Agamben/Lewis’s concept of study see: Vlieghe and Zamojski ( 2019 ).

Agamben, G. 1998. Homo sacer: Sovereign power and bare life . (D. Heller-Roazen, Trans.) Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Arendt, H. 2003. Thinking and moral considerations. In Responsibility and judgment (J. Kohn, Ed.). New York: Schocken. (Original work published 1971)

Bacon, F. 2000. The new organon (L. Jardine & M. Silverthorne, Trans.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1620)

Bell, D. 1976. The coming of post-industrial society . New York: Basic Books.

Book   Google Scholar  

Biesta, G.J.J. 2006. Beyond learning: Democratic education for a human future . Boulder: Paradigm.

Google Scholar  

Dahlgren, L., G. Handal, T. Szkudlarek, and M. Bayer. 2007. Students as journeymen between cultures of higher education and work: A comparative European project on the transition from higher education to working life. Higher Education in Europe 32 (4): 305–316.

Article   Google Scholar  

Delors, J. et al. 1996. Learning: The treasure within. Report to UNESCO of the International Commission on Education for the Twenty-first Century. UNESCO Publishing, Retrieved on 5 February 2020, from https://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0010/001095/109590eo.pdf .

Etzkowitz, H., and L. Leydesdorff. 1997. Universities and the global knowledge economy: A triple helix of university-industry-government relations . London: Pinter.

European Commission 2005. EU research on social sciences and humanities. Students as Journeymen between communities of higher education and work. Journeymen Final report , HPSE-CT-2001-00068. Retrieved from https://cordis.europa.eu/documents/documentlibrary/82608291EN6.pdf .

FP 6 Specific Programme “Integrating and Strengthening the European Research Area” Priority 7: Citizens and Governance in a knowledge based society Work Programme 2004–2006. Retrieved on 24 March 2020, from https://docs.google.com/viewer?url=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.europafacile.net%2FFormulari%2F6PQricerca%2FBandi%2FIntegrareSpazioEuropeoRicerca%2FFP6-2004-CITIZENS_4e5e6%2Fg_wp_200202_en.pdf&pdf=true .

Heidegger, M. 1962. Being and time . (J. MacQuarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (Original work published 1927)

Heidegger, M. 1968. What is called thinking? (F. D. Wieck & J. Glenn Gray, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row. (Original work published 1952)

Heidegger, M. 1971. The thing. In Poetry, language, thought (A. Hofstadter, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row. (Original work published 1950)

Heidegger, M. 1973. Overcoming metaphysics. In The end of philosophy (J. Stambaugh, Trans). New York: Harper & Row. (Original work published 1954)

Heidegger, M. 1977a. The question concerning technology. In The question concerning technology and other essays (W. Lovitt, Trans.). New York: Garland.

Heidegger, M. 1977b. Science and reflection. In M. Heidegger, The question concerning technology and other essays (W. Lovitt, Trans.). New York: Garland.

Heidegger, M. 2000. Überwindung der Metaphysik. In M. Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe. Band 7: Vorträge und Aufsätze . Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Vittorio Klostermann. (Original work published 1951)

Heidegger, M. 2002. Was heißt denken? In M. Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe. Band 8: Was Heißt Denken? Frankfurt am Main, Germany: Vittorio Klostermann. (Original work published 1952)

Hoskin, K. 1990. The crypto-educationalist unmasked. In Foucault and education: Disciplines and knowledge , ed. S. Ball, 29–53. London: Routledge.

Jessop, B. 2007. Knowledge as a fictitious commodity: Insights and limits of a Polanyian analysis. In Reading Karl Polanyi for the 21st century: Market economy as a political project , ed. A. Buğra and K. Ağartan, 115–134. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Jessop, B. 2008. A cultural political economy of competitiveness and its implications for higher education. In Education and the knowledge-based economy in Europe , ed. B. Jessop, N. Fairclough, and R. Wodak, 13–40. Rotterdam: Sense.

Laclau, E. 2005. On populist reason . London: Verso.

Laclau, E. 2014. The rhetorical foundations of society . London: Verso.

Leitch, S., and J. Roper. 1998. Genre colonization as a strategy: A framework for research and practice. Public Relations Review 24(2): 203–218.

Lewis, T. 2015. On Study: Giorgio Agamben and Educational Potentiality . London: Routledge.

Masschelein, J. 1996. Individualization, singularization and e-ducation (Between indifference and responsibility). Studies in Philosophy and Education 15: 97–105.

Masschelein, J. & Simons, M. 2013. In Defence of the school: A public issue (J. McMartin, Trans.). Leuven, Belgium: E-ducation, Culture & Society.

Marx, K. 1999 [1887]. Capital: A critique of political economy . Volume I, Book One: The Process of Production of Capital. Online Version: Marx/Engels Internet Archive (marxists.org) 1995, 1999. Retrieved March 6, 2020 https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ .

Neef, D. 2009. Introduction: Re-thinking economics in the knowledge-based economy. In The economic impact of knowledge , ed. D. Neef, G.A. Siesfield, and J. Cefola, 3–16. Woburn: Butterworth-Heinemann.

Phillips, D. 2005. Economics as ideological fantasy. Dispensability of man by way of changing the nature of ideas. International Journal of Applied Semiotics 4(2): 9–34.

Proctor, R.N., and L. Schiebinger (eds.). 2008. Agnotology: The making and unmaking of ignorance . Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Rancière, J. 1991. The ignorant schoolmaster. Five lessons in intellectual emancipation (K. Ross, Trans.) . Stanford: Stanford University Press. (Original work published 1987)

Rancière, J. 1999. Dis-agreement: Politics and philosophy (J. Rose, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. (Original work published 1995)

Rancière, J. 2010. Dissensus: On politics and aesthetics (S. Corcoran, Ed. & Trans). London: Continuum.

Roberts, J., and J. Armitage. 2008. The ignorance economy. Prometheus 26 (4): 335–354.

Standing, G. 2011. The precariat: The new dangerous class . London: Bloomsbury Academic.

Stankiewicz, Ł. 2018. Wizje uniwersytetu w polskiej debacie publicznej 2007–2009 [Visions of the University in the Polish Public Debate in the Years 2007–2009] . Kraków: Impuls.

Szkudlarek, T. 2010. Inner university, knowledge workers, and liminality. In The Routledge doctoral student's companion: Getting to grips with research in education and social sciences , ed. P. Thompson and M. Walker, 356–367. London: Routledge.

Szkudlarek, T. 2016. On the Politics of Educational Theory: Rhetoric, theoretical ambiguity, and the constructions of society . New York: Routledge.

Vlieghe, J. 2013. Experiencing (im)potentiality: Bollnow and Agamben on the educational meaning of school practices. Studies in Philosophy and Education 32(2): 189–203.

Vlieghe, J., and P. Zamojski. 2019. Towards an ontology of teaching. Thing-centred pedagogy, affirmation and love for the world . Cham: Springer.

Zeller, C. 2008. From the gene to the globe: Extracting rents based on the intellectual property monopolies. Review of International Political Economy 15(1): 86–115.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

University of Gdańsk, Gdańsk, Poland

Tomasz Szkudlarek & Piotr Zamojski

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tomasz Szkudlarek .

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ .

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Szkudlarek, T., Zamojski, P. Education and Ignorance: Between the Noun of Knowledge and the Verb of Thinking. Stud Philos Educ 39 , 577–590 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-020-09718-9

Download citation

Published : 29 March 2020

Issue Date : November 2020

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-020-09718-9

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Knowledge-based society
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research
  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Social History
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Strategy
  • Business Ethics
  • Business History
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic History
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • Ethnic Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Qualitative Political Methodology
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Virtue and Happiness: Essays in Honour of Julia Annas

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

PLATO ON THE POWER OF IGNORANCE

  • Published: August 2012
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

In Book V of Plato’s Republic , Plato has Socrates distinguish between three distinct cognitive powers ( dunameis ): knowledge ( epistēmē ), opinion ( doxa ), and ignorance ( agnosia ). Powers, Socrates goes on to explain, are distinguished in virtue of what they are related to and what they accomplish ( eph hōi te esti kai hō apergazetai --477d1). In this section of the dialogue, the second of these two differentiae is not invoked again; instead, all of the distinctions Socrates makes here are made in terms of the different objects to which the powers are related. Knowledge, we are told, is related to what is (to on); ignorance is related to what is not (to mē on); opinion is related to what both is and is not.Scholars have attended almost entirely to the distinction between knowledge and opinion, and for good reason: It is clear that this distinction is the primary one that Plato wishes to explicate here, as it is in terms of this distinction that the important difference between the philosopher rulers and ordinary rulers will be drawn. The distinctions between knowledge and ignorance and opinion and ignorance are only very briefly mentioned, and ignorance itself remains almost wholly unexplained. This chapter discusses the role of ignorance in Plato’s epistemology. This chapter's analysis is novel in four ways: First, other scholars have attended almost exclusively to the roles assigned to knowledge and opinion in this passage, and have neglected to explain whether — and if so, how — their analyses could explicate what Plato has Socrates say about ignorance. Secondly, the chapter argues that we should not understand the ‘related to’ part of Plato’s analysis as an intensional one: cognitive powers are not ‘of’ or ‘about’ the objects to which they are related, as scholars have generally supposed. The relationship of the powers to objects, rather, is a nomological one. Thirdly, I argue that what is produced by the cognitive powers are what we would call conceptualizations (or conceptions) of the entities to which they are said to be related ( epi ). Finally, the chapter argues that the case of ignorance makes clear that the ‘is’ in Plato’s analysis of the relata of each cognitive power must be understood neither veridically (where ‘is’ means ‘is true’), nor existentially (where ‘is’ means ‘exists’), but predicatively (where ‘is’ means ‘is F,’ where F is the name of a Platonic Form).

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

Month: Total Views:
October 2022 10
November 2022 14
December 2022 9
January 2023 9
February 2023 15
March 2023 14
April 2023 5
May 2023 8
June 2023 7
July 2023 4
August 2023 5
September 2023 7
October 2023 5
November 2023 12
December 2023 10
January 2024 3
February 2024 8
March 2024 10
April 2024 13
May 2024 9
June 2024 10
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Last updated 27/06/24: Online ordering is currently unavailable due to technical issues. We apologise for any delays responding to customers while we resolve this. For further updates please visit our website: https://www.cambridge.org/news-and-insights/technical-incident

We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings .

Login Alert

ignorance and knowledge essay

  • < Back to search results
  • The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance

The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance

ignorance and knowledge essay

  • Get access Buy a print copy Check if you have access via personal or institutional login Log in Register
  • Cited by 18

Crossref logo

This Book has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by Crossref .

  • Google Scholar
  • Edited by Rik Peels , Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam , Martijn Blaauw , Technische Universiteit Delft, The Netherlands
  • Export citation
  • Buy a print copy

Book description

Ignorance is a neglected issue in philosophy. This is surprising for, contrary to what one might expect, it is not clear what ignorance is. Some philosophers say or assume that it is a lack of knowledge, whereas others claim or presuppose that it is an absence of true belief. What is one ignorant of when one is ignorant? What kinds of ignorance are there? This neglect is also remarkable because ignorance plays a crucial role in all sorts of controversial societal issues. Ignorance is often thought to be a moral and legal excuse; it is a core concept in medical ethics and debates about privacy, and it features in religious traditions and debates about belief in God. This book does not only study an epistemic phenomenon that is interesting in itself, but also provides important tools that can be fruitfully used in debates within and beyond philosophy.

  • Aa Reduce text
  • Aa Enlarge text

Refine List

Actions for selected content:.

  • View selected items
  • Save to my bookmarks
  • Export citations
  • Download PDF (zip)
  • Save to Kindle
  • Save to Dropbox
  • Save to Google Drive

Save content to

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to .

To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle .

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service .

Save Search

You can save your searches here and later view and run them again in "My saved searches".

The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance pp i-ii

  • Get access Check if you have access via personal or institutional login Log in Register

The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance - Title page pp iii-iii

Copyright page pp iv-iv, dedication pp v-vi, contents pp vii-viii, introduction pp 1-11.

  • By Rik Peels , Martijn Blaauw

1 - The Nature of Ignorance: Two Views pp 12-32

  • By Pierre Le Morvan , Rik Peels

2 - The Varieties of Ignorance pp 33-56

  • By Nikolaj Nottelmann

3 - Ignorance and Incompetence: Linguistic Considerations pp 57-80

  • By Berit Brogaard

4 - Explicating Ignorance and Doubt: A Possible Worlds Approach pp 81-95

  • By Erik J. Olsson , Carlo Proietti

5 - Ignorance and Epistemic Contextualism1 pp 96-113

  • By Michael Blome-Tillmann

6 - Anti-Intellectualism and Ignorance pp 114-131

  • By Jessica Brown

7 - Ignorance and Epistemic Value pp 132-143

  • By Duncan Pritchard

8 - Ignorance and the Religious Life pp 144-159

  • By Justin McBrayer

9 - Epistemic Injustice and the Preservation of Ignorance pp 160-177

  • By Miranda Fricker

10 - Ignorance and Racial Insensitivity pp 178-201

  • By José Medina

References pp 202-214

Index pp 215-217, altmetric attention score, full text views.

Full text views reflects the number of PDF downloads, PDFs sent to Google Drive, Dropbox and Kindle and HTML full text views for chapters in this book.

Book summary page views

Book summary views reflect the number of visits to the book and chapter landing pages.

* Views captured on Cambridge Core between #date#. This data will be updated every 24 hours.

Usage data cannot currently be displayed.

Essay Service Examples Life Ignorance

Ignorance Is Bliss: Essay

  • Proper editing and formatting
  • Free revision, title page, and bibliography
  • Flexible prices and money-back guarantee

document

Our writers will provide you with an essay sample written from scratch: any topic, any deadline, any instructions.

reviews

Cite this paper

Related essay topics.

Get your paper done in as fast as 3 hours, 24/7.

Related articles

Ignorance Is Bliss: Essay

Most popular essays

  • Literary Criticism

Choices exist in everyday life, beginning with the time of birth until the time of death and...

  • Vaccination

Vaccination is the way how to prevent humanity before infection diseases. It is beneficial in...

  • Film Analysis

Active ignorance is described by Mills as lacking confinement to those who are uneducated, but is...

Ignorance is usually an ability that any person would now not know. In truth, lack of knowledge is...

  • Fahrenheit 451
  • Ray Bradbury

The famous playwrighter William Shakespeare once said, “There is no darkness, but ignorance.”...

  • Animal Farm
  • George Orwell

In societies where members of the elite class have access to tools that the majority do not, the...

According to the Merriam-Webster dictionary, ignorance is defined as the lack of knowledge or...

Plato’s view on immorality is ignorance is derived from the argument put forward in ‘Protagoras’...

Motivation is definitely important for everyone to achieve success in whatever field. But the...

Join our 150k of happy users

  • Get original paper written according to your instructions
  • Save time for what matters most

Fair Use Policy

EduBirdie considers academic integrity to be the essential part of the learning process and does not support any violation of the academic standards. Should you have any questions regarding our Fair Use Policy or become aware of any violations, please do not hesitate to contact us via [email protected].

We are here 24/7 to write your paper in as fast as 3 hours.

Provide your email, and we'll send you this sample!

By providing your email, you agree to our Terms & Conditions and Privacy Policy .

Say goodbye to copy-pasting!

Get custom-crafted papers for you.

Enter your email, and we'll promptly send you the full essay. No need to copy piece by piece. It's in your inbox!

University of Notre Dame

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews

  • Home ›
  • Reviews ›

Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy

Placeholder book cover

James M. Ambury and Andy German (eds.), Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy , Cambridge University Press, 2019, 274pp., $105.00 (hbk), ISBN 9781107184466.

Reviewed by Christopher Moore, Penn State University

The problem of self-knowledge is a reasonable candidate for the core problem of philosophy. It serves as a good nexus for epistemology, metaphysics, and ethics and for approaches from all corners of the discipline. It keeps the inquiry somewhat below the heavens. And it makes sense of Socrates as an exemplary figure, one who strives, with analytic acuity, to undermine conceits and doctrinal self-confidence. The as-yet-unresolved difficulties constituting the problem of self-knowledge fall into at least two overlapping historical groups. There are those programmatic in contemporary epistemology, connected to warrant for first-person knowledge of occurrent mental states. These include matters of evidence, justification, and specification of the knowable mental states: the general question is, given the differences between apprehending facts in the outer and the mental worlds, how can both kinds of fact-apprehension count as knowledge?

The other difficulties are those best known from ancient Greek philosophy, connected to the kind of thing the self must be to stand both as a subject and object of knowledge. These include whatever limits on reflexivity there may be; the nature of selfhood and its relation to psuchê , desires, reason, and individuality; and the degree to which “knowing oneself” really amounts to coming to be able to know (anything) and coming to be a self (rather than jumble of instincts, impressions, and reactions). The general question here is, given the range of things one could strive to know — e.g., human norms, the will of the gods, cosmic patterns — what makes striving to know oneself both possible and beneficial? Plato’s dialogues reflect a lifetime of his and Socrates’ explicit and productive attention to these latter problems of self-knowledge. But if self-knowledge were a core problem in (ancient) philosophy, we might expect more scholarship directed at it — and not just bromides about the gnôthi sauton and the therapeutic effects of the so-called elenchus.

This feeling of a lack motivates the volume edited by James M. Ambury and Andy German. One of the book’s strengths is that it shows issues of self-knowledge to suffuse Plato’s works, emphasizing Alcibiades , Apology , Charmides , Phaedrus , Republic , Symposium , Theaetetus , and Theages , and giving some attention to Laws , Meno , Parmenides , Philebus , and Sophist . The editors also have the salutary goal of including chapters “from very different interpretative principles.” A weakness of the book, however, is that this breadth and openness serves no specifically articulated program of investigation and, as we will see, mostly foregoes dialectical engagement with others in and out of Plato studies concerned about self-knowledge. Too often papers end up being isolated, if edifying, readings of specific dialogues on the theme of knowledge of oneself. I turn to those chapters, with the upshot for self-knowledge, below. First, the title and introduction.

This book’s title, Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy , is neither entirely idiomatic nor entirely apt (the editors really only speak of “self-knowledge” and a bit about “self-ignorance”); but no matter - maybe it’s better for search results. “Platonic” serves rather than “Plato’s” to indicate studies of the dialogues of doubted authenticity and of Proclus, a ("neo")Platonist. I do query the final word, “Philosophy”: why not “Dialogues”? Most chapters explicate dialogues rather than articulate, against or in conversation with other philosophers, for example Heraclitus or Aristotle or Kant, a “Platonic” “philosophy,” as a distinctive program or result of inquiry. There are exceptions, to be sure, and the editors are free to believe that Plato has views that can be recovered. Despite their claim, however, I don’t think the book really aims to “highlight the relevance of Plato’s thought to contemporary debates on selfhood, self-reflection, and subjectivity.”

The introduction is part of the problem. It opens with some high paragraphs about “a certain loss of confidence in modernity’s philosophical conception of . . . ‘selfhood’ as such” and the motivation to return to Plato’s thinking about “our capacity for becoming . . . an object of our own interior reflection . . . without our . . . now-questionable concept of subjectivity.” It soon leaves that (unpromising) theme for a list of some topics in relation to which Plato seems to think about self-knowledge, including the pursuit of desire, psychic structure, the nature of thinking, and the educability of the soul.

But is there really value in thinking specifically about Plato on self-knowledge? I see two related ways to show it. Ambury and German could have shown that Plato’s works clarify, rejigger, even resolve ongoing philosophical problems of, say, self-determination, the discovery of human nature, or the evaluation of one’s commitments. For example: Sartre’s idea that thinking of oneself as a source of action as one thought too many; Moran’s analysis of self-knowledge as determined through investigation rather than discovered through introspection. Or the editors could have shown that existing scholarship on Plato has developed important questions internal to Plato’s work that can be satisfactorily dealt with only by thinking about self-knowledge.

Neither route gets followed here. The introduction almost wholly avoids scholarly engagement: it cites only five works, almost in passing and none by name, as proving a burgeoning industry in the topic. On the first page, the editors write: “Doubtless there has been a sea change in the three decades since Julia Annas’ diagnosis that Plato’s interest in self-knowledge ‘faded’ as he graduated to a more mathematical conception of ἐπιστήμη and its objects.” They mean Annas’ 1985 “Self-Knowledge in Early Plato.” It no longer represents the state of the art; but it is a great chapter in an edited collection, and deserves its frequent citation, for the very reason that it advances a determinate multi-part thesis with which one can engage: what counts as “self-knowledge” (she famously defines it, with Bradley, as knowing “one’s stations and duties”), what role it plays in the arguments of Plato’s dialogues, how it can be identified with justice, and the way other concepts end up playing its role, for good reasons, in certain of Plato’s dialogues. Even though I, for one, would take issue with each part, the paper brilliantly articulates an anxiety I have concerning the limits on the usefulness of the concept of “self-knowledge” in Plato. Disappointingly, Annas’ paper never arises again in this book.

On page 7, Ambury and German cite the other four works. No content is ascribed to Edward Ballard’s Socratic Ignorance: An Essay on Platonic Self-Knowledge (1965), dismissed simply as “outdated” despite having a “masterful command of the topic.” Nor is content ascribed to Charles Griswold’s Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus (1986) or Andrea Tschemplik’s Knowledge and Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Theaetetus (2008), both dismissed for concerning only single dialogues: but for the unitarian, so what? Similarly, no content is ascribed to my own Socrates and Self-Knowledge (2015), dismissed as concentrating “exclusively” on Socrates (in Charmides , Alcibiades , Phaedrus , and Philebus ), though given the centrality of Socrates to each of this volume’s thirteen chapters, and the way, arguably, Plato develops his views through the conversations of Socrates, I don’t see the problem. Thus the introduction does not provide a dialectical justification for studying Plato on self-knowledge, and does not bring a reader up-to-speed on, or remind a fellow laborer about, the still-urgent topics in the field.

I belabor the editors’ underuse of scholarship because it is symptomatic for the volume. Four chapters have effectively no explicit engagement with others (Lloyd P. Gerson, Drew A. Hyland, Jeremy Bell, Eric Sanday); two others have minimal engagement (Thomas Tuozzo, Sara Ahbel-Rappe); the rest point to parallel discussions by other scholars without engaging concertedly with them. Does this mavericity betray the Socratic-Platonic vision of self-knowledge as adhering to a regimen of reciprocal examination, a recognition of our epistemic feebleness and the godsend in finding others who might teach us something? (There is no index entry for “self-knowledge, and conversation.”)

Onto the chapters now, which follow no editorially specified order.

1. Gerson, “Self-Knowledge and the Good.”  Self-knowledge is the recognition of (= knowledge of and identification with) one’s ideal self, which is one’s reason or intellect, as opposed to some merely apparent self, for example the subject of one’s occurrent desires. Knowing oneself involves making judgments about one’s desires, assessing whether they aim at the actual rather than merely apparent good. Thus self-knowledge, a real achievement, also requires knowledge of the form of the good. “Self-knowledge is the mediating idea between the metaphysics of the Good and the way of life that is philosophy.” Whatever metaphysical commitments coming to know oneself actually requires, this paper enunciates — efficiently, provocatively, and persuasively — the core commitment of Platonic self-knowledge: the self is a normative self, constituted by its rational commitments to the good and the true. Many of the subsequent chapters adopt this view, even if silently or indirectly. Unlike some of the following chapters, however, this one demonstrates that one can talk of Platonic self-knowledge without talk of psuchê (“soul”), which seems often to become a lexical redundancy.

2. Tuozzo, “Two Faces of Platonic Self-Knowledge: Alcibiades I and Charmides .”  Though the Alcibiades focuses on knowledge of self and, by contrast, the Charmides focuses on knowledge of itself , these dialogues end up with compatible and mutually illuminating views of self-knowledge. Tuozzo gives insightful and convincing readings of each dialogue to show this. (A Gersonian shortcut not here taken: if the self is a knowing self, then a person’s knowledge of herself as knower is both a knowledge of oneself and a knowledge of knowledge.) Consistency between two dialogues matters little on its own terms; Tuozzo goes on to claim that both dialogues concern a knowledge that “is strictly speaking good for a human being.” This is an important claim; it seeks an answer to the question posed by Socrates in the Charmides and Alcibiades in the Alcibiades : what value is there in the reflexive or hierarchical state of knowing knowledge? Is it not empty because redundant? This is a question many of the subsequent chapters address, even if (again) silently or indirectly. An answer in the context of these two dialogues should have something to do with sôphrosunê , the virtue of “discipline” that serves as the Charmides ’ focal concept and Alcibiades ’ argumentative pivot, in both dialogues equated, at least tentatively, with self-knowledge.

3. Hyland, “Socratic Self-Knowledge and the Limits of Epistêmê .”  Self-knowledge is not a mode of epistêmê (“knowledge”); it must be some other epistemic state. This is argued on the basis of the Charmides , with Hyland claiming that the view that self-knowledge as an epistêmê of epistemai (etc.) is shown to be impossible but that “Socratic self-knowledge” — knowing what one knows and does not know — is not. The dialogue does show something unsatisfactory about Critias’ analysis of self-knowledge as a second-order epistêmê on the model of the various fields of knowledge, such as medicine and geometry. But it seems to me that the Socratic inflection, which is merely personalized and treated in terms of the verb eidenai , fares no better in the argument, even if Socrates shows its possibility through his actions. There are other mistaken or misleading statements in this through-reading of the dialogue. It refers to virtually no scholarship other than Hyland’s 1981 book on the Charmides — itself inspirational for the time, uniquely putting the dialogue at the center of philosophical reflection, but one not benefited from the nearly four decades of rigorous and textually sensitive attention to the dialogue since its publication. Hyland does not even acknowledge the existence of Tuozzo’s work in the preceding chapter or his field-changing 2011 study of the dialogue.

4. Ahbel-Rappe, “Socratic Wisdom and Platonic Knowledge in the Dialogues of Plato.”  Self-knowledge is both high wisdom and empty: it is not the knowledge of any object of knowledge — i.e., any mental content — but rather of knowing itself, the “container” or judge of those contents. Comments about the Charmides and a successful description of the latter parts of the Theaetetus advance the two parts of this claim. It is not an easy argument to follow, lacking dialectical engagement with any surrounding chapters. But thematic continuity exists: with Hyland, the knowledge constituting Socrates’ wisdom or self-knowledge differs from the usual sorts of knowledge; with Tuozzo, it is somehow reflexive but not too reflexive; with Gerson, it is an essential feature of one’s conception of oneself as knower.

5. James M. Ambury, “Between Ascent and Descent: Self-Knowledge and Plato’s Allegory of the Cave.”  Each level of the divided line in Republic Book 6 corresponds to a type of self-knowledge. “Eikastic”: I see my shadow as me . “Aporetic”: I see my shadow as a shadow of me, but I do not know what I am. “Dianoetic”: I see myself as once having been confused about myself, and am pleased about my newfound self-understanding. “Intellective”: I know myself in my knowing, a subject and not mere object of knowledge. This chapter also explains why philosophers have to “return to the cave”: full self-knowledge recognizes that one is not purely an intellective being, and so one cannot live solely with intellectual objects. I did not feel particularly assisted in seeing how the four-fold taxonomy maps onto practical life. Would, too, that there had been engagement with the only other recent paper on self-knowledge in the Republic , Mary Margaret McCabe’s “From the Cradle to the Cave: What Happened to Self-Knowledge in the Republic?” ( Platonic Conversations , 2015).

6. Brian Marrin, “Self-Knowledge and the Use of the Self in the Platonic Theages. ”  Self-knowledge amounts, finally, to knowing what to do with oneself, what final end to pursue. Marrin argues from a thought-experiment about the tyrant who can do anything , unobstacled, but whose freedom makes salient his ignorance about its use, and from the drama of the Theages , which includes Socrates’ famous knowledge of ta erôtika as “his capacity for uncovering for his interlocutors the true nature of their desires.” We have returned yet again to self-knowledge as the clarification of and identification with one’s fundamental desires: the recovery of a (normative) self.

7. Sara Brill, “Between Biography and Biology: Bios and Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus .”  We are to know ourselves not just as selves or souls but as end-directed lives , where knowing one’s “life” or “manner of life” includes knowing one’s political context and attitude toward truth. For all its complications, this chapter goes beyond its predecessors in dwelling on self-knowledge’s possible connection with our temporal extension, practical identity, and (thus) teleological narrative dimension. While not responding to the debate about “impersonal” vs. “idiosyncratic” selves ultimately to be known, it rightly asks us to think about the kinds of people we are who attribute to ourselves a “self”: people who live through time in patterned and more or less organized fashions.

8. Bell, “A Toil-Loving Soul.”  The good and self-knowing life is active and awake, principally in thinking about the virtues and oneself. A sententious and sometimes tendentious chapter (I doubt Plato’s predecessors so lauded sleep), it at least resonates with Brill’s paper, cheering lives lived actively. Yet I could not tell whether Bell believes self-knowledge achievable , even if through continuous activity.

9. Andy German, “Mathematical Self-Ignorance and Sophistry: Theodorus and Protagoras.”  Mathematics does not on its own improve one’s understanding of virtue. Paradoxically, in its prizing of clarity, it can seduce one into failing to see its inadequacy. This is a not unfamiliar lesson of the Theaetetus . We return, again, to the necessary normativity of self-knowledge: we must know what is good .

10. Marina McCoy, “Why is Knowledge of Ignorance Good?”  When aporia leads to recognition of one’s limitations, it can encourage the pursuit of knowledge, and it can lead to greater generosity with others. Yet, McCoy claims, pointing to the Meno , recognizing one’s ignorance does not always motivate inquiry. Obscured by much summary of dialogues is a good question: when does it so motivate? McCoy emphasizes the “affective” dimension, though I wonder whether, in conversation with the volume’s other authors, she would accept the language of “discovery (or obfuscation) of one’s deeper desires.”

11. Sanday, “Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Symposium .”  Recognition of limits and the affective recur here: “Through eros, human beings exceed the limit that defines them, and at the same time they become aware of being subject to that limit and learn to attend to it properly.” Because of erôs , talk of beauty may be called for: “Self-knowledge, or virtue simply, would consist of a life of sustained and appreciative letting-presence of the beautiful.” This is an edifying and provocative idea, bringing “beauty” onto the self-knowledge scene, even if Sanday does not connect it up with the concerns of his volume-companions. Yet the connections ought to be drawn out, since he believes, with nearly all of them, that “the question of self-knowledge is whether we are choosing our lives in light of ultimate reasons or causes, and thereby, living seriously.”

12. Danielle A. Layne, “Double Ignorance and the Perversion of Self-Knowledge.”  “Double ignorance,” by contrast with “recognized ignorance,” is failing to know what you fail to know, and this is a grave political danger. More intriguingly, the failure of love (of oneself and others) causes (and is caused by?) the failure of knowledge (of oneself and others).

13. Harold Tarrant, “ Philebus , Laws , and Self-Ignorance”  Plato’s concerns about self-knowledge changed across his career. The Philebus focuses only on self-ignorance; in the late dialogues generally “there is no real interest . . . in self-knowledge as a key to any of the virtues.” Earlier dialogues treat self-knowledge as “a deep awareness of the very core of our being or . . . the foundations for virtue.” Tarrant reasons at least from the Phaedrus , though the previous twelve chapters (etc.) give cause to qualify the contrast. Tarrant draws this distinction less to explicate any particular view than to show that the Alcibiades , as a “deeper truths” dialogue, would not be written late in Plato’s career (as Nicholas Denyer, in an influential commentary, has argued). He makes a similar claim about Alcibiades II .

Here I conclude. Despite all the editors’ talk of diverse approaches and the contributors’ ignorance of each other’s work, the chapters generally share important commitments: we should consider the self to be normative; distinguish the “object” of self-knowledge from that of other kinds of knowledge; treat humans as ideal epistemic agents and practical agents; foreground the concept of “one’s life”; and meditate on love and beauty.

A final and dour observation about the book’s production. The end matter has terribly many fundamental errors, indicating no editorial oversight. The main text should also have received (more) rigorous proofreading, with more than two dozen mistakes, often in the spelling of Greek words. The unprincipled toggling between Greek font and transliteration distracts.

24/7 writing help on your phone

To install StudyMoose App tap and then “Add to Home Screen”

The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance

Save to my list

Remove from my list

The Developmental Role of Ignorance

writer-marian

The Knowledge-Ignorance Dualism: A Complex Scenario

The paradox of knowledge and happiness, conclusion: navigating the complexity of knowledge and ignorance.

The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance. (2016, Aug 07). Retrieved from https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay

"The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance." StudyMoose , 7 Aug 2016, https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay

StudyMoose. (2016). The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay [Accessed: 29 Jun. 2024]

"The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance." StudyMoose, Aug 07, 2016. Accessed June 29, 2024. https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay

"The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance," StudyMoose , 07-Aug-2016. [Online]. Available: https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay. [Accessed: 29-Jun-2024]

StudyMoose. (2016). The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/definition-essay-on-ignorance-essay [Accessed: 29-Jun-2024]

  • Unraveling the Pages of "Fahrenheit 451": A Dystopian Tale of Knowledge and Ignorance Pages: 2 (582 words)
  • The Veil of Ignorance: A Journey to Knowledge and Liberation Pages: 2 (599 words)
  • Arrogance and Ignorance in Jon Krakauer’s Into The Wild Pages: 3 (752 words)
  • Chris McCandless: An Odyssey of Ignorance and Consequences Pages: 2 (579 words)
  • Ignorance to Enlightenment in Fahrenheit 451 and Uglies Pages: 3 (896 words)
  • Obliviousness And Ignorance in Benito Cereno By Herman Melville Pages: 4 (1120 words)
  • The Symbolism of Blindness in "Oedipus": Ignorance, Denial, and Truth Pages: 2 (448 words)
  • The Issue Of Moral Ignorance Pages: 7 (1928 words)
  • Cosi: Challenging Our Ignorance About Mental Illness Pages: 4 (1180 words)
  • Choosing Blindness: A Dive into Willful Ignorance Pages: 3 (603 words)

The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance essay

👋 Hi! I’m your smart assistant Amy!

Don’t know where to start? Type your requirements and I’ll connect you to an academic expert within 3 minutes.

Home — Essay Samples — Life — Ignorance — A Study on the Truth Behind the Saying “Ignorance is Bliss”

test_template

A Study on The Truth Behind The Saying "Ignorance is Bliss"

  • Categories: Ignorance

About this sample

close

Words: 1571 |

Published: Jan 4, 2019

Words: 1571 | Pages: 3 | 8 min read

Works Cited

  • Plato. (380 BCE). Republic (Book VII). (J. Harward, Trans.). Project Gutenberg. (Original work published in Greek)
  • Palmer, D. (2011). Does the prisoner in Plato's Cave have a theory of forms? Polis: The Journal for Ancient Greek Political Thought, 28(1), 104-128.
  • Descartes, R. (1641). Meditations on First Philosophy. (J. Cottingham, Trans.). Cambridge University Press. (Original work published in French)
  • Scruton, R. (2015). Plato's allegory of the cave. A Short History of Modern Philosophy: From Descartes to Wittgenstein, Routledge.
  • Gill, M. L. (2017). The allegory of the cave. In R. E. Auxier & L. E. Hahn (Eds.), The philosophy of Thomas Reid (pp. 343-354). Routledge.
  • Berman, D. (2019). Knowledge is power: The impact of information on society. Scientific American.
  • Sartre, J. P. (1944). Existentialism is a humanism. (P. Mairet, Trans.). Methuen Publishing.
  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Williams and Norgate.
  • McLeod, S. A. (2017). Skinner - Operant conditioning. Simply Psychology.
  • Lao Tzu. (n.d.). Tao Te Ching. (J. Legge, Trans.). Sacred Texts. (Original work published in Chinese)

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Life

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

6 pages / 2752 words

2 pages / 990 words

2 pages / 785 words

2 pages / 1179 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

A Study on The Truth Behind The Saying "Ignorance is Bliss" Essay

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Ignorance

In Rowson’s Charlotte Temple and Rowlandson’s The Sovereignty and Goodness of God, ignorance plays a big role in the character developments and trials they face. Although Rowson and Rowlandson wrote in different time periods and [...]

Is it wrong for someone to be held accountable for their ignorance if their actions accidentally cause harm to others? Factual Ignorance can be defined as when someone does something morally wrong because they don’t know or [...]

Do you believe that ignorance is truly bliss? In today's fast-paced world, where information is constantly at our fingertips, the notion of ignorance being bliss may seem appealing. However, upon closer examination, it becomes [...]

In Fahrenheit 451 by Ray Bradbury, the protagonist, Guy Montag, works as a fireman that burns books rather than putting out fires, like a fireman is intended to do. Montag starts out as a loyal citizen to the society, burning [...]

Have you ever wanted to go exploring out in the wild all by yourself? If so you might want to change your mind. Based on Jon Krakauer’s novel, “Into the wild”, the author explores the life of a young man named Chris McCandless [...]

Swirlies, nugees, wet willies, wedgies. We’ve all heard of them and some of us have had the unfortunate luck of experiencing them. If you are like me, when I was a 12 year old in 6th grade it was common to see “locker vandalism” [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

ignorance and knowledge essay

IMAGES

  1. Knowledge Vs Ignorance Fahrenheit 451 Essay

    ignorance and knowledge essay

  2. The Challenge of Striking the Right Balance Between Ignorance and

    ignorance and knowledge essay

  3. The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance Free Essay Example

    ignorance and knowledge essay

  4. Ignorance vs Knowledge: When To Use Each One In Writing?

    ignorance and knowledge essay

  5. Ignorance stems from lack of knowledge.: [Essay Example], 3986 words

    ignorance and knowledge essay

  6. Knowledge and Horizon of Ignorance Essay Example

    ignorance and knowledge essay

VIDEO

  1. a saying about ignorance and exploitation

  2. KNOWLEDGE IS POWER Essay|10 sentences

  3. ignorance : lack of knowledge, understanding, or information about something

  4. All Problems Are ILLUSION And Your Mind Creates Them

  5. Session-1: Ethics And Essay Enrichment Class

  6. Essay on Knowledge is Power

COMMENTS

  1. Ignorance and Knowledge in Fahrenheit 451 by Ray Bradbury

    Get custom essay. There are countless ways to explain the use of Ignorance and knowledge in Bradbury's novel Fahrenheit 451. It is concluded that ignorance is brought out through distraction, people believe that ignorance leads to an easier life. A life that is controlled brings out all the unhappiness in the.

  2. Ignorance Essays: Samples & Topics

    Examples Of Ignorance Is A Bliss And Origin Of The Word. 2. Knowledge & Understanding Of Ignorance In A Bible. 3. The Philosophy Of Ignorance And Knowledge In Buddhism. 4. Motives That Drive People Towards Discrimination. 5. An Essay on Liberal Arts and Sciences: Ignorance is Bliss. 6. The Invisible Man: The Problem of Social Blindness and ...

  3. Knowledge and Ignorance

    Introduction. Knowledge and Ignorance is a central theme in philosophy and has been explored by many thinkers throughout history. Here are some of the most important axes related to this topic: Epistemology: Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that deals with knowledge and belief. This axis would explore different theories of knowledge ...

  4. Plato: 'Ignorance, the root and stem of all evil.'

    This powerful quote by Plato encapsulates the inherent relationship between knowledge and morality. In its straightforward interpretation, the quote suggests that ignorance is the fundamental cause of all wrongdoing and immorality. When individuals lack knowledge or understanding, they are more likely to engage in harmful actions or contribute ...

  5. Opinions: Knowledge or ignorance

    Here are two from favorite writers of mine. Hippocrates commented: "Science is the father of knowledge, but opinion breeds ignorance.". Surely he refers to folks who offer opinions willy nilly ...

  6. Understanding Ignorance: The Surprising Impact of What We Don't Know

    Highlights from this section include a very effective cartography metaphor that illuminates interactions between knowledge and ignorance: they shape one another, the boundary between them is often vague, and shifts, and it can be created naturally or artificially. The author also provides a nice inventory of empirical and philosophical research ...

  7. Ignorance and Lack of Knowledge

    Essay Example: Ignorance and lack of knowledge can lead to other forms of slavery in today's society. Teaching how to think, not what to think will lead to a healthier, more productive society. Better critical thinking prevents social outcasts and helps us to grow in culture. Frederick Douglass

  8. Argument Essay Ignorance is not Bliss

    However, upon closer examination, it becomes clear that ignorance can lead to significant consequences. This argument essay will delve into the idea that ignorance is not bliss, exploring how a lack of knowledge can be detrimental in various aspects of life. By examining the impact of ignorance on personal relationships, decision-making, and ...

  9. Ignorance Essays

    Ignorance Essays. Essay examples. Essay topics. 15 essay samples found. Sort & filter. 1 A Study on The Truth Behind The Saying "Ignorance is Bliss" 3 pages / 1571 words . ... Ignorance is the lack of knowledge on a subject caused by not being exposed to the information. Whereas stupidity is the inability to gain knowledge about a subject.

  10. Introduction: Histories of Ignorance

    that ignorance is more than a simple negative of knowledge and that ignorance—like knowledge, objectivity, facts, truth, scholarly virtues, etc.—has a history of its own, albeit a slightly stranger one. In fact, together the essays suggest that, in order to fully understand human knowledge's past, one also needs to trace why and

  11. Ignorance Free Essay Examples And Topic Ideas

    10 essay samples found. Ignorance denotes a lack of knowledge, awareness, or understanding. Essays on ignorance might explore its psychological, social, or philosophical dimensions, its impact on individual and collective decision-making, or the societal mechanisms that perpetuate ignorance. Discussions might also delve into the concept of ...

  12. Education and Ignorance: Between the Noun of Knowledge and ...

    In this paper we look at the relations between knowledge and thinking through the lens of ignorance. In relation to knowledge, ignorance becomes its "constitutive outside," and as such it may be politically organised in order to delimit the borders of the right to knowledge [the "ignorance economy," see Roberts and Armitage (Prometheus 26 (4): 335-354, 2008)]. In this light, the ...

  13. PLATO ON THE POWER OF IGNORANCE

    But in book 5 of the Republic Plato provides an analysis of ignorance that seems to violate these truisms. Starting at 476 E 4 he has Socrates and Glaucon distinguish between three distinct cognitive powers (dunameis): 1 knowledge (epistēmē), belief (doxa), and ignorance (agnōsia).Powers, Socrates goes on to explain, are distinguished in virtue of what they are related to (I will henceforth ...

  14. Knowledge, Ignorance and True Belief

    Let us call the thesis that knowledge and ignorance are opposites the "Complement Thesis". In this article, I discuss its deployment in an ingenious new argument advanced by Alvin Goldman and Erik Olsson (2009) which, if sound, establishes that there is a kind of knowledge that amounts to nothing more than true belief.

  15. The Epistemic Dimensions of Ignorance

    Ignorance is a neglected issue in philosophy. This is surprising for, contrary to what one might expect, it is not clear what ignorance is. Some philosophers say or assume that it is a lack of knowledge, whereas others claim or presuppose that it is an absence of true belief. What is one ignorant of when one is ignorant?

  16. PDF The only good is knowledge and the only evil is ignorance

    which an increase in knowledge leads to success. Why This Essay Received a Score of 4 This is a solid, well-organized essay that has a clear focus ("Knowledge is absolutely crucial to success") and discusses the main idea with three competent body paragraphs. Each paragraph contains specific examples ("Lance Armstrong and

  17. Ignorance Is Bliss: Essay

    A basic human nature is to keep on gaining knowledge, so by deliberately, of your free will, keeping yourself out of knowledge and into a false state of ignorance, you are stupid. "Ignorance is bliss" means something different to each individual. ... Ignorance Is Bliss: Essay. (2022, December 27). Edubirdie. Retrieved June 28, 2024, from ...

  18. Knowledge and Ignorance of Self in Platonic Philosophy

    On page 7, Ambury and German cite the other four works. No content is ascribed to Edward Ballard's Socratic Ignorance: An Essay on Platonic Self-Knowledge (1965), dismissed simply as "outdated" despite having a "masterful command of the topic."

  19. Full article: Who Were the Ignorant? Reflections on Actors, Marginality

    This review essay explores the issue of actors and ignorance, which leads to questions concerning marginality, hierarchies, agency, and the use and value of knowledge and knowing. The essay draws on Peter Burke's telling examples and adds some of its own to discuss ignorance from a different perspective, arguing that while we should recognise ...

  20. The Connection Between Lack of Knowledge and Foolishness: [Essay

    The Connection Between Lack of Knowledge and Foolishness. Categories: Ignorance. Words: 915 | Pages: 2 | 5 min read. Published: Jan 4, 2019. Ignorance is the lack of knowledge on a subject caused by not being exposed to the information. Whereas stupidity is the inability to gain knowledge about a subject. While ignorance and stupidity are often ...

  21. The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance Free Essay Example

    The Duality of Knowledge and Ignorance. When faced with information that challenges our beliefs, the inclination to retreat into the comforting phrase "ignorance is bliss" is a common human response. However, it is crucial to recognize that ignorance is not a state of true bliss; rather, it serves as a temporary anesthetic that eventually wears ...

  22. Ignorance Essay: Knowledge Vs. Ignorance

    Ignorance Essay: Knowledge Vs. Ignorance; Ignorance Essay: Knowledge Vs. Ignorance. Superior Essays. 972 Words; 4 Pages; Open Document. Essay Sample Check Writing Quality. Show More. Knowledge vs. Ignorance Adam and Job are knowledge-seeking people, but for different reasons. Adam is inexperienced, and like a child, he is naturally curious ...

  23. Essay On Ignorance

    Many people live by the phrase "knowledge is power" while others comfortably believe in the saying "ignorance is bliss". According to Juan D. Carrillo and Thomas Mariotti, some people would rather be ignorant because "voluntary ignorance [can] be used as a self-control device preventing the individual from embarking in a hazardous activity which he [or she] could later regret ...

  24. A Study on The Truth Behind The Saying "Ignorance is Bliss"

    Ignorance And Knowledge In Fahrenheit 451 By Ray Bradbury Essay In Fahrenheit 451 by Ray Bradbury, the protagonist, Guy Montag, works as a fireman that burns books rather than putting out fires, like a fireman is intended to do.

  25. PDF Disinformation in Science: Ethical Considerations for Citing Retracted

    the individuals who cited retracted papers in our study were knowledge creators who receive professional credit and prestige for publishing papers, bringing "first-hand" knowledge of phenomena to the world (Wilson, 1983). ... The ethics of ignorance, missing information, misinformation, disinformation and other forms of deception or ...